Why do some people have a strange desire to do weird things for no (good) reason? There's something fascinating about kids who eat laundry soap as part of a “challenge,” or people who deliberately... Read more
The question in Part I was: what is the nature of religious credence (or “belief”) as a psychological state? And a puzzle arose because neither the simple model nor the cynical model of religious “belief” was adequate. To rehash, the psychological data from Justin Barrett and Frank Keil show this: people think, remember, and reason about God in ways that go contrary to their professed religious “beliefs.” The puzzle is this: what then shall we say about those “beliefs”? Do people really believe them?
The simple model, recall, says that religious people who profess that God is (say) omnipresent simply believe that God is everywhere, just like you or I believe grass is green. The cynical model says that the religious who profess this don’t believe it; they are only pretending to believe. The simple model seems wrong, because it suggests the psychological data should be other than they are; the cynical model seems wrong, because it fails to capture the sincerity of religious “belief”—most people who profess religious commitment, it seems, are not lying about what they “believe.” So what shall we say?
My proposal contrasts with both models. According to the religious credence model, there are in fact two distinct internal mental attitudes—superficially similar—both of which often go by the name “belief.” But they differ in important respects on close inspection. If I’m right, then saying that the religious do or don’t “believe” in omnipresence (the simple model or the cynical model) will be misleading either way.
Consider two so-called “beliefs.” One is in the mind of James, who isn’t up to speed on which world leaders are still alive. The other is in the mind of Terry, a devout Christian:
- James believes# Margaret Thatcher is alive.
- Terry believes* Jesus Christ is alive.
James remembers famous leaders and, in a matter of fact way, takes some to be alive and others not. But Terry regards the contents she “believes” with reverence; she regards them in a way that makes her attitude part of her very identity. So the attitudes expressed by “believes#” and “believes*” are different. Accordingly, the religious credence model posits two different kinds of attitudes, factual belief and religious credence.
Let’s return to the Barrett and Keil study and the so-called “belief” in God’s omnipresence. Recall that people who professed this “belief” tended to remember and reason as though they represented God as limited in time and space.
My model says that people who profess God’s omnipresence typically have a religious credence that God is everywhere, even though they do not have a factual belief to this effect. And this lack of factual belief partly accounts for the experimental results. Barrett goes on in another work to argue that our intuitive beliefs about agency also tend to represent agents, including gods, as limited, contrary to one’s “theologically correct beliefs.” On my view, Barrett’s theologically correct beliefs are a subset of the wider class of religious credences.
Now two questions arise. First, what features exactly differentiate religious credence from factual belief? Second, how different really is the credence model from the cynical model? (After all, I am saying that the so-called “believer” doesn’t factually believe the religious propositions in question.)
I can’t go into full detail on the first question—let alone provide suitable arguments—but here’s a sketch of my view.
Factual belief is the attitude we mostly take toward mundane contents that help us navigate the world, like there is a ditch in front of me or Oregon is north of California. Factual beliefs are available for guiding inferences and actions in all practical settings, and they tend to be extinguished by evidence contrary to them. Even if we’re in a special setting—like in church or on stage—we use factual beliefs to track the objects and events around us.
Religious credences, by way of contrast, give one a sense of virtue and direction in life, whenever one uses them to guide actions. Credences also play a role in constituting one’s social identity. On the flip side, however, they typically don’t guide action when one’s life direction, religion, or social identity is not in question. Have you ever heard the phrase “once a week Christian”? This phrase captures the idea, now backed by anthropological research, that many religious “beliefs” (credences) don’t guide behavior outside certain special situations. Furthermore, religious credences do not tend to be extinguished by evidence in the way that factual beliefs are. Rather, evidence that would seem to go contrary to religious credences gets folded into a larger religious narrative.
This all allows us now to answer the second question. On the cynical model, the religious agent is lying about her beliefs—merely pretending. On the credence model, the religious agent sincerely holds a positive attitude that gives social and moral orientation in her life. It is not the case on the credence model that the religious agent knowingly believes contrary to her credences (as the cynical model would suggest). Rather, those “beliefs” (credences!) are just an importantly different kind of state altogether.
Comments (5)
Laura Maguire
Sunday, September 28, 2014 -- 5:00 PM
Neil, perhaps this is justNeil, perhaps this is just the simple model (though I'm not sure) but one way to account for the empirical data that Barrett and Keil gather is simply to say that religious believers hold contradictory beliefs. Depending on the context, they straightforwardly believe that God is and is not omnipresent. This would not be the first time in history that a human being simultaneously held conflicting beliefs, and it seems like a natural interpretation of the data. So, I'm wondering what motivates the alternative theories, including your own credence model and the competing cynical model. These only seem to get off the ground if we reject the idea that believers are just irrationally holding contradictory beliefs.
Or perhaps you want to remain neutral on the question of rationality? Given that in your model, a factual belief and a religious credence are different kinds of attitudes with different relations to evidence, could they ever be said to conflict with one another?
R. Cats
Saturday, October 4, 2014 -- 5:00 PM
It is very possible that noIt is very possible that no two people on the planet share the same understanding and vision of God; and yet share the same religion. Creeds are created by groups (usually men) and then made part of a religion. A good test of personal belief is behavior; however there are factors that may cause one to behave against his/her belief.
Neil Van Leeuwen
Monday, October 13, 2014 -- 5:00 PM
Hi Laura,Hi Laura,
Good question. Why not just posit contradictory beliefs? The key point, I think, is that the contradictory theological "beliefs" don't just go away *even when the person holding them realizes the inconsistency* (see Barrett 1999). But for our mundane, everyday factual beliefs, realization of inconsistency is a death knell. Say you believe your bike is in the garage; then your buddy calls and says he borrowed the bike to visit the park. Assuming you believe your buddy, your first belief is immediately extinguished. You do not go on holding the contradictory beliefs that the bike is and isn't in the garage. The realization of inconsistency extinguishes one belief or the other. This reliance on consistency to maintain our ordinary class of factual beliefs is so constant that it mostly goes unnoticed in everyday life. But it is real. So given that, we must ask ourselves what is going on when we see apparent breaks in the reliance on consistency when it comes to "belief" maintenance, breaks that the subject even notices. And one answer is that a different attitude is present altogether. We are not bothered when our imaginings are inconsistent with our factual beliefs (usually)--not being bothered by inconsistency is just a sign that a different sort of attitude is present. Apply this reasoning to the Barrett data! Thanks for the question :)
mwsimon
Saturday, October 18, 2014 -- 5:00 PM
Is the difference betweenIs the difference between beliefs and credences to be found in what motivates them, or in what kind of actions they motivate? You talk some about how beliefs influence our actions and decisions while credences give us a sense of virtue and direction. I think it is more fundamental to their differing natures that beliefs are motivated by perception and logical thought, while credences are motivated by faith. Perhaps I am being unfair - there could be some logic behind credence. What do you think?
Guest
Thursday, September 1, 2016 -- 5:00 PM
Instantly amazed with all theInstantly amazed with all the useful information that is on it. Great post, just what I was looking for and I am looking forward to reading your other posts soon. I honestly think you would have fully sold me on the idea had you been able to back up your premise with a substantial bit more solid facts. Great piece of writing and a great link you provide. Thanks you so much, I appreciate your work. Feel free stuf (http://www.essayguardian.com/)