Humans: The Irrational Animal
Jun 29, 2004Some psychologists claim to have demonstrated that humans are systematically, deeply and perhaps irredeemably irrational in their reasoning and decision making.
Classic theories of choice posit that our preferences are transitive. That sounds fancy, but the idea is straightforward. It means that if you prefer A to B and B to C, then you’ll also prefer A to C. For example, if you prefer the apple to the orange and the orange to the banana, then you’ll also prefer the apple to the banana.
Now one interesting question in psychology is the extent to which human preferences actually conform to such axioms as transitivity. There are many complications that arise on that issue. For example, as Daniel Kahneman says, “People don’t choose between things. They choose between descriptions of things.” And this means that insofar as humans do conform to transitivity, this conformity will be complicated by psychological phenomena like frame effects, endowment effects, and many other cognitive biases.
But it’s fair to say that, for ordinary day-to-day choices, human choice tends to be transitive to a great enough extent that it’s at least worth investigating and trying to explain any apparent transitivity failures that arise.
Most transitivity failures, it seems, will be merely apparent. Say I offer you a choice between three pieces of cake and two, and you prefer three. Then I offer you a choice between two and one, and you prefer two. But then when I offer you a choice between one and three, you pick one.
This at first blush seems like a transitivity failure (3>2 and 2>1, but it’s not true that 3>1). But it’s easily explained by the likely social dynamics of the situation: someone faced with a choice between three and one pieces of cake may worry about appearing greedy, so when they choose the one piece of cake, it’s not just a matter of 1>3. Rather, it’s [1+not appearing greedy] > 3, which means that transitivity hasn’t strictly been violated. They probably would still prefer three pieces two one, if there were no risk of appearing greedy.
What’s interesting about all this is that apparent transitivity failures generate psychological hypotheses that can be tested empirically. Here, the hypothesis would be that the person who chose the one piece of cake is concerned about the appearance of greed, which can presumably be tested by various empirical measures, such as (surprise, surprise) simply asking the person.
With all that as background, I’d like to pose a puzzle about preferences that concern sacred values, which I first discovered when reading anthropologist Scott Atran’s astonishing 2010 book Talking to the Enemy.
Atran does extensive work in psychology as well as anthropology. And out of interest in understanding what motivates religious terrorists, he set out to Indonesia in the early 2000s (just after 9/11) to study the Islamic fundamentalist terrorists there who were engaged in a religious war with Christian communities. Amazingly, the terror cells let him in and even gave him a guide who was one of their members.
As you’d expect, the book that emerged is a fascinating piece of anthropological research. Atran, after all, was a protégé of Margaret Mead, and he lives up to the expectations that pedigree would set.
One of the questions Atran asked of his terrorist informants was designed to assess whether sacred values (sacred preferences, choices, etc.) operate the way ordinary utilitarian values do. And one issue he looked at was transitivity.
Here’s the problem he gave his informants, who all regarded both jihad and pilgrimage to Mecca as sacred. In each choice presented, they would have to choose between two of the three options, which were as follows:
The results were surprising: the choices were intransitive—or at least apparently so.
Atran’s informants generally thought that 2 was better than 1. That is, it’s better to do an equally effective non-suicide attack than a suicide attack.
When they were given the choice between 2 and 3, they tended to choose 3. That is—somehow not surprisingly—going on a pilgrimage to Mecca should take priority over a non-suicide attack.
So far, we have 3>2 and 2>1. Transitivity would thus lead us to think that 3>1 in this case.
But when given the choice between 3 and 1…they chose 1! Martyrdom, apparently, is more choiceworthy than pilgrimage.
So 3>2 and 2>1, but 1>3. Transitivity, apparently, is violated.
Atran interprets this as further evidence that sacred values don’t function like ordinary utilitarian preferences. He’s most likely right about that, and a lot of other evidence suggests the same.
But is he licensed in his conclusion that, as he puts it, “sacred values aren’t transitive”?
There are two options here. First, Atran is right that they’re just not transitive, which would seem to imply that sacred values—from a rational standpoint—are far more mysterious than we might have thought. But second, maybe this is somehow analogous to the cake case, where the apparent violation of transitive preferences is merely apparent, meaning there’s an implicit aspect of the choice that’s not mentioned in one of the scenarios.
I have my own solution to this problem. But for now I want to leave it as a puzzle so I can see what you think.
So is it the first option (sacred values are intransitive and mysterious)? Or the second option (there’s a tacit aspect of the choice in one of the scenarios that’s not obvious at first glance and keeps transitivity from being violated)?
If you go with the first option, it’s incumbent on you to say what you think the advantage is to an organism’s being designed—in Dennett’s sense of design without a designer—in a way that includes intransitive values (which seems an odd design feature to say the least). If you go with the second, it’s incumbent on you to say what the tacit feature is that saves this pattern of choices from being a violation of transitivity.
So, what do you think?
Comments (1)
Harold G. Neuman
Friday, August 30, 2019 -- 12:21 PM
This plays somewhatThis plays somewhat complementarily into an essay currently under consideration by this writer. I think sacred values may or may not exhibit transitivity, in the same sense that magic and religion sprang from similar aspects of human development, including ignorance; fear; intolerance and something Jaynes called the bicameral mind. Magic and religion have traditionally had their roles in explaining the unexplainable; unravelling mysteries; and giving reasons for things which defy reason. My essay will examine this and a bit more, finally arriving at a 'reductio', (ad absurdum, or otherwise). Whether sacred values are (or are not) transitive depends, at least in part, on how many adherents they may have attracted over time---the worldwide congregations of the major religions speaks to this notion: sacred values for Christianity and Islam, for example, are more meaningful(and,therefore, transitive) than those held by, say, The Church of the Weeping Prostitute. They will influence far more people for a longer time and will probably out-perform those of the followers of the lady of the evening. In mentioning aspects of human development, I intentionally omitted the grounding for all of those; that grounding which erupts from ignorance and fear: superstition.
Superstition leads men to all sorts of rationalizations. Magic and religion are forms of such rationalization, because men desperately need to believe in something. But John Dewey said that beliefs are 'shady'. Other philosophers of status have offered similar assessments. And so, sacred values that have withstood the tests of time and persecution; values upon which plenitudes agree and have agreed; attain transitivity, while lesser ones evaporate under the weakness of the doctrines that espoused them: it is not the strength of the dog in the fight but the strength of the fight in the dog. Dennett's notion of design-without-a-designer is not unique. Others (including Dawkins) have said much the same thing in slightly different words. Long before modern day scholars, evolutionists were saying the same thing, while dodging the wrath of the churchmen. But, you already know all of that.
Best Regards,
Neuman